DOC

Heidegger_Being_and_Time_13

By Lawrence Lawrence,2014-07-20 05:13
7 views 0
being and time for the time being heidegger at the time being for time being time being martin heidegger the time being time and date love and time

    AUTHOR'S NOTES

    Foreword

    i. ( H. 1 ) Plato, Sophistes244a.

    Introduction, Chapter One

    i. ( H. 3 ) Aristotle, Metaphysica B 4, 1001 a 21.

     1ii. ( H. 3 ) Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica 11 Q. 94 art. 2.

iii. ( H. 3 ) Aristotle, Metaphysica B 3, 998 b 22.

     6iv. ( H. 4 ) Cf. Pascal, Pensées et Opuscules (ed. Brunschvicg), Paris, 1912, p. 169; 'On ne

    peut entreprendre de définir l'être sans tomber dans cette absurdité: car on ne peut définir

    un mot sans commencer par celui-ci, c'est, soit qu'on l'exprime ou qu'on le sous-entende.

    Donc pour définir l'être, il faudrait dire c'est, et ainsi employer le mot défini dans sa

    définition.'

v. ( H. 6 ) Plato, Sophistes 242c.

vi. ( H. 14 ) Aristotle, De Anima Γ8, 431 b 21; cf. ibid. Γ5, 430 a 14 ff .

vii. ( H. 14 ) Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones de Veritate, q. I, a 1 c; cf. the somewhat different

    and in part more rigorous way in which he carries out a 'deduction' of the transcendentia in

    his opuscule 'De Natura Generis'.

    Introduction, Chapter Two 2i. ( H. 23 ) I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, pp. 180 f.

ii. ( H. 26 ) Aristotle, Physica Δ 10-14 (217b 29-224a 17).

iii. ( H. 26 ) I. Kant, op. cit., p. 121.

iv. ( H. 32 ) Cf. Aristotle, De Interpretatione1-6; also Metaphysica Z4, and Ethica Nicomachea

    Z

    v. ( H. 38 ) If the following investigation has taken any steps forward in disclosing the things

    themselves', the author must first of all thank E. Husserl, who, by providing his own incisive

    personal guidance and by freely turning over his unpublished investigations, familiarized

    the author with the most diverse areas of phenomenological research during his student

    years in Freiburg.

    Division One, Chapter One

    i. ( H. 44 ) St. Augustine, Confessiones, X, 16. ['But what is closer to me than myself?

    Assuredly I labour here and I labour within myself; I have become to myself a land of

    trouble and inordinate sweat.'Tr.]

    ii. ( H. 44 ) Edmund Husserl's investigations of the 'personality' have not as yet been

    published. The basic orientation of his problematic is apparent as early as his paper

    "Philosophic als strenge Wissenschaft", Logos, vol. I, 1910, p. 319. His investigation was

    carried much further in the second part of his Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und

    phänomenologischen Philosophie (Husserliana IV), of which the first part (Cf. this

    Jahrbuch [ Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische ForschungTr.] vol. I,

    1913), presents the problematic of 'pure consciousness' as the basis for studying the

    Constitution of any Reality whatsoever. His detailed Constitutional analyses are to be found

    in three sections of the second part, where he treats: 1. the Constitution of material Nature;

    2. the Constitution of animal Nature; 3. the Constitution of the spiritual world (the

    personalistic point of view as opposed to the naturalistic). Husserl begins with the words:

    'Although Dilthey grasped the problems which point the way, and saw the directions which

    the work to be done would have to take, he still failed to penetrate to any decisive

    formulations of these problems, or to any solutions of them which are methodologically

    correct.' Husserl has studied these problems still more deeply since this first treatment of

    them; essential portions of his work have been communicated in his Freiburg lectures.

    -489-

    iii. ( H. 47 ) This Jahrbuch, vol. I, 2, 1913, and II, 1916; cf. especially pp. 242 ff.

iv. ( H. 47 ) Ibid., II, p. 243 .

v. ( H. 47 ) Cf. Logos I, loc. cit.

vi. ( H. 48 ) Ibid., p. 246 .

    vii. ( H. 48 ) Genesis I, 26. ['And God said, "Let us make man in our image, after our likeness."

    'Tr.)

viii. ( H. 49 ) Calvin, Institutio I, XV, Section 8. ['Man's first condition was excellent because of

    these outstanding endowments: that reason, intelligence, prudence, judgment should suffice

    not only for the government of this earthly life, but that by them he might ascend beyond,

    even unto God and to eternal felicity.'Tr.]

ix. ( H. 49 ) Zwingli. Von der Klarheit des Wortes Gottes ( Deutsche Schriften I, 56). ['Because

    man looks up to God and his Word, he indicates clearly that in his very Nature he is born

    somewhat closer to God, is something more after his stamp, that he has something that

    draws him to Godall this comes beyond a doubt from his having been created in God's

    image.'Tr.]

x. ( H. 50 ) But to disclose the a priori is not to make an 'a-prioristic' construction. Edmund

    Husserl has not only enabled us to understand once more the meaning of any genuine

    philosophical empiricism; he has also given us the necessary tools. 'A-priorism' is the

    method of every scientific philosophy which understands itself. There is nothing

    constructivistic about it. But for this very reason a priori research requires that the

    phenomenal basis be properly prepared. The horizon which is closest to us, and which must

    be made ready for the analytic of Dasein, lies in its average everydayness.

    xi. (H. 51) Ernst Cassirer has recently made the Dasein of myth a theme for philosophical

    Interpretation. (See his Philosophie der symbolischen Formen, vol. II, Das mythische

    Denken, 1925.) In this study, clues of far-reaching importance are made available for

    ethnological research. From the standpoint of philosophical problematics it remains an open

    question whether the foundations of this Interpretation are sufficiently transparent

    whether in particular the architectonics and the general systematic content of Kant's

    Critique of Pure Reason can provide a possible design for such a task, or whether a new and

    more primordial approach may not here be needed. That Cassirer himself sees the

    possibility of such a task is shown by his note on pp. 16 ff., where he alludes to the

    phenomenological horizons disclosed by Husserl. In a discussion between the author and

    Cassirer on the occasion of a lecture before the Hamburg section of the Kantgesellschaft in

    December 1923 on 'Tasks and Pathways of Phenomenological Research', it was already

    apparent that we agreed in demanding an' existential analytic such as was sketched in that

    lecture.

    Division One, Chapter Two

    i. ( H. 54 ) Cf. Jakob Grimm, Kleinere Schriften, vol. VII, p. 247.

ii. ( H. 56 ) Cf. Section 29.

    Division One, Chapter Three

    i ( H. 72 ) The author may remark that this analysis of the environment and in general the

    'hermeneutic of the facticity' of Dasein, have been presented repeatedly in his lectures since

    the winter semester of 1919-1920.

    ii. ( H. 77 ) Cf. E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen

    Philosophie, I. Teil, this Yearbook [ Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische

    Forschung] vol. I, Section 10 ff., as well as his Logische Untersuchungen, vol. I, Ch. 11.

    For the analysis of signs and signification see ibid., vol. II, I, Ch. 1 .

iii. ( H. 90 ) Descartes, Principia Philosophiae, I, Pr. 53. ( œuvres, ed. Adam and Tannery, vol.

    VIII, p. 25.) ['And though substance is indeed known by some attribute, yet for each

    substance there is pre-eminently one property which constitutes its nature and essence, and

    to which all the rest are referred.'Tr.]

    iv. ( H. 90 ) Ibid. ['Indeed extension in length, breadth, and thickness constitutes the nature of

    corporeal substance! The emphasis is Heidegger's.Tr.]

v. ( H. 90 ) Ibid. ['For everything else that can be ascribed to body presupposes extension!

    Tr.]

vi. ( H. 90 ) Ibid., Pr. 64, p. 31 . ['And one and the same body can be extended in many

    different ways while retaining the same quantity it had before; surely it can sometimes be

    greater in length and less in breadth or thickness, while later it may, on the contrary, be

    greater in breadth and less in length.'Tr.]

    -490-

    vii. ( H. 91 ) Ibid., Pr. 65, p. 32 . ['. . . if we think of nothing except what has a place, and do not

    ask about the force by which it is set in motion . . .'Tr.]

    viii. ( H. 91 ) Ibid., II, Pr. 4. p. 42 . ['For, so far as hardness is concerned, the sense shows us

    nothing else about it than that portions of hard bodies resist the movement of our hands

    when they come up against those portions. For if whenever our hands are moved towards a

    certain portion, all the bodies there should retreat with the same velocity as that with which

    our hands approach, we should never feel any hardness. Nor is it in any way intelligible that

    bodies which thus recede should accordingly lose their corporeal nature; hence this does not

    consist in hardness.'Tr.]

    ix. ( H. 91 ) Ibid. ['And by the same reasoning it can be shown that weight and colour and all

    the other qualities of this sort which are sensed in corporeal matter, can be taken away from

    it, while that matter remains entire; it follows that the nature of this depends upon none of

    these.'Tr.)

    x. ( H. 92 ) Ibid., I, Pr. 51, p. 24 . ['Indeed we perceive that no other things exist without the

    help of God's concurrence.'Tr].

    xi. ( H. 92 ) Ibid. [. . . only one substance which is in need of nothing whatsoever, can be

    understood, and this indeed is God.'Tr.]

    xii. ( H. 92 ) Ibid. ['Indeed we perceive that other things cannot exist without the help of God's

    concurrence.'Tr.]

    xiii. ( H. 93 ) Ibid. [The complete passage may be translated as follows: 'The name "substance"

    is not appropriate to God and to these univocally, as they say in the Schools; that is, no

    signification of this name which would be common to both God and his creation can be

    distinctly understood.'Tr.]

xiv. ( H. 93 ) In this connection, cf. Opuscula omnia Thomae de Vio Caietani Cardinalis,

    Lugduni, 1580, Tomus III, Tractatus V; 'de nominum analogia', pp. 211-219.

    xv. ( H. 93 ) Descartes, op. cit., I, Pr. 51, p. 24. ['No signification of this name <"substance">

    which would be common to God and his creation can be distinctly understood.'Tr.]

    xvi. ( H. 94 ) Ibid., I, Pr. 52, p. 25 . ['Yet substance cannot first be discovered merely by the fact

    that it is a thing that exists, for this alone by itself does not affect us.'Tr.]

    xvii. ( H. 94 ) Ibid., I, Pr. 63, p. 31 . ['Indeed we understand extended substance, or thinking

    substance more easily than substance alone, disregarding that which thinks or is

    extended.'Tr.]

    xviii. ( H. 96 ) Ibid., II, Pr. 3, p. 41 . ['It will be enough if we point out that the perceptions of the

    senses are not referred to anything but the union of the human body with the mind, and that

    indeed they ordinarily show us in what way external bodies can be of help to it or do it

    harm.'Tr.]

xix. ( H. 97 ) Ibid., II, Pr. 3, pp. 41-42 . ['. . . but they do not teach us what kinds of things

    bodies> exist in themselves.'Tr.]

    xx. ( H. 97 ) Ibid., II, Pr. 4, p. 42 . ['If we do this, we shall perceive that the nature of matter, or

    of body as regarded universally, does not consist in its being something hard or heavy or

    coloured or affecting the senses in some other way, but only in its being something

    extended in length, breadth, and thickness.'Tr.]

xxi. ( H. 109 ) Immanuel Kant: "Was Heisst:"Sich im Denken orientieren? ( 1786) Werke (Akad.

    Ausgabe), Vol. VIII, pp. 131-147.

    xxii. ( H. 112 ) Cf. O. Becker, Beiträge zur phänomenologischen Begründung der Geometrie und

    ihrer physikalishen Anwendungen, in this Yearbook [ Jahrbuch für Philosophie und

    phänomenologische Forschung], vol. VI ( 1923), pp. 385 ff.

    Division One, Chapter Four

    i. ( H. 116 ) Cf. what Max Scheler has pointed out phenomenologically in his Zur

    Phänomenologie und Theorie der Sympathiegefühle, 1913, Anhang, pp. 118 ff.; see also his

    second edition under the title Wesen und Formen der Sympathie, 1923, pp. 244 ff.

ii. ( H. 119 ) "Über die Verwandtschaft der Ortsadverbien mit dem Pronomen in einigen

    Sprachen" ( 1829), Gesammelte Schriften (published by the Prussian Academy of Sciences),

    vol. VI, Part 1, pp. 304-330.

    Division One., Chapter Five

    i. ( H. 131 ) Cf. Section 12, H. 52 ff.

ii. ( H. 131 ) Cf. Section 13, H. 59-63.

iii. ( H. 137 ) Cf. Section 18, H. 83 ff.

iv. ( H. 138 ) Cf. Aristotle, Metaphysica A 2, 982 b 22 sqq. ['comfort and recreation' Ross].

    -491-

    v. ( H. 139 ) Cf. Pascal, Pensées, [ed. Brunschvicg, Paris, p. 185]. 'Et de là vient qu'au lieu

    qu'en parlant des choses humaines on dit qu'il faut les connaître avant que de les aimer, ce

    qui a passé en proverbe, les saints au contraire disent en parlant des choses divines qu'il

    faut les aimer pour les connaître, et, qu'on, n'entre dans la vérité que par la charité, dont ils

    ont fait une de leurs plus utiles sentences.' ['And thence it comes about that in the case

    where we are speaking of human things, it is said to be necessary to know them before we

    love them, and this has become a proverb; but the saints, on the contrary, when they speak

    of divine things, say that we must love them before we know them, and that we enter into

    truth only by charity; they have made of this one of their most useful maxims'.Tr.) Cf.

    with this, Augustine, Opera, ( Migne Patrologiae Latinae, tom. VIII), Contra Faustum, lib.

    32, cap. 18: 'non intratur in veritatem, nisi per charitatem.' ['one does not enter into truth

    except through charity'.Tr.]

vi. ( H. 140 ) Cf. Aristotle, Rhetorica B 5, 1382 a 20-1383 b 11.

vii. ( H. 143 ) Cf. Section 18, H. 85 ff.

viii. ( H. 147 ) Cf. Section 4, H. 11 ff.

ix. ( H. 156 ) Cf. Section 13, H. 59 ff.

x. ( H. 166 ) On the doctrine of signification, cf. Edmund Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen,

    vol. II, Investigations I, IV-VI. See further the more radical version of the problematic in his

    Ideen I, Sections 123 ff., pp. 255 ff.

xi. ( H. 171 ) Aristotle, Metaphysica A 1, 980 a 21 x.

xii. ( H. 171 ) Augustine, Confessiones, X, 35.

xiii. ( H. 175 ) Cf. Section 9, H. 42 ff.

    Division One, Chapter Six

    i. ( H. 180 ) Cf. Section 12, H. 52 ff.

ii. ( H. 188 ) Cf. Section 12, , H. 53 ff.

iii. ( H. 189 ) Cf. Section 27, H. 126 ff.

    iv. ( H. 190 ) It is no accident that the phenomena of anxiety and fear, which have never been

    distinguished in a thoroughgoing manner, have come within the purview of Christian

    theology ontically and even (though within very narrow limits) ontologically. This has

    happened whenever the anthropological problem of man's Being towards God has won

    priority and when questions have been formulated under the guidance of phenomena like

    faith, sin, love, and repentance. Cf. Augustine's doctrine of the timor castus and servilis,

    which is discussed in his exegetical writings and his letters. On fear in general cf. his De

    diversis quaestionibus octoginta tribus, qu. 33 (de metu); qu. 34 (utrum non aliud amandum

    sit, quam metu carere); qu. 35 (quid amandum sit). ( Migne, Patrologiae Latinae tom. VII,

    pp. 23 ff.)

    Luther has treated the problem of fear not only in the traditional context of an Interpretation

    of poenitentia and contritio, but also in his commentary on the Book of Genesis, where,

    though his treatment is by no means highly conceptualized, it is all the more impressive as

    edification. Cf. Enarrationes in genesin, cap. 3, Werke( Erlanger Ausgabe ), Exegetica

    opera latina, tom. I, pp. 177 ff.

    The man who has gone farthest in analysing the phenomenon of anxietyand again in the

    theological context of a 'psychological' exposition of the problem of original sinis Soren

    Kierkegaard. Cf. Der Begriff der Angst (The Concept of Dread], 1844, Gesammelte Werke

    ( Diederichs), vol. 5.

v. ( H. 197 ) The author ran across the following pre-ontological illustration of the existential-

    ontological Interpretation of Dasein as care in K. Burdach's article. "Faust und die Sorge"

    ( Deutsche Vierteljahrschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte, vol. I, 1923,

    pp. 1 ff.). Burdach has shown that the fable of Cura (which has come down to us as No. 220

    of the Fables of Hyginus) was taken over from Herder by Goethe and worked up for the

    second part of his Faust. Cf. especially pp. 40 ff. The text given above is taken from F.

    Bücheler ( Rheinisches Museum, vol. 41, 1886, p. 5); the translation is from Burdach, Ibid.,

    pp. 41 ff .

vi. ( H. 198 ) Cf. Herder's poem: "Das Kind der Sorge" (Suphan XXIX, 75).

vii. ( H. 199 ) Burdach, op. cit., p. 49. Even as early as the Stoics, μριμνα was a firmly

    established term, and it recurs in the New Testament, becoming "sollicitudo" in the Vulgate.

    The way in which care' is viewed in the foregoing existential analytic of Dasein, is one

    which has grown upon the author in connection with his attempts to Interpret the

    Augustinian (i.e., Helleno-Christian) anthropology with regard to the foundational

    principles reached in the ontology of Aristotle.

    -492-

    viii. ( H. 201 ) Cf. H. 89 ff. and H. 100.

     2ix. ( H. 203 ) Cf. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, pp. 274 ff., and further the corrections

    added in the preface to the second edition, p. xxxix, note: see also 'On the Paralogisms of

    the Pure. Reason', ibid., pp. 399 ff., especially p. 412 .

x. ( H. 203 ) Ibid. , Preface, note.

xi. H. 203 ) Ibid., p. 275 .

xii. ( H. 203 ) Ibid., p. 275 .

xiii. .( H. 204 ) Ibid., p. 275 .

xiv. ( H. 205 ) Ibid., Preface, note .

     xv. ( H. 205 ) Cf. W. Dilthey, "Beiträge zur Lösung der Frage vorn Ursprung unseres

    Glaubens an die Realität der Aussenwelt und seinem Recht" ( 1890), Gesammelte

    Schriften, Vol. V, i, pp. 90 ff. At the very beginning of this article Dilthey says in no

    uncertain terms: 'For if there is to be a truth which is universally valid for man, then in

    accordance with the method first proposed by Descartes, thought must make its way from

    the facts of consciousness rather than from external actuality.' ( Ibid., p. 90 .)

xvi. ( H. 208 ) Following Scheler's procedure, Nicolai Hartmann has recently based his

    ontologically oriented epistemology upon the thesis that knowing is a 'relationship of

    Being'. Cf. his Grundzüge einer Metaphysik der Erkenntnis, second enlarged edition,

    1925. Both Scheler and Hartmann, however, in spite of all the differences in the

    phenomenological bases from which they start, fail to recognize that in its traditional basic

    orientation as regards Dasein, 'ontology' has been a failure, and that the very 'relationship

    of Being' which knowing includes (see above, H. 59 ff.), compels such 'ontology' to be

    revised in its principles, not just critically corrected. Because Hartmann underestimates the

    unexpressed consequences of positing a relationship-of-Being without providing an

    ontological clarification for it, he is forced into a 'critical realism' which is at bottom quite

    foreign to the level of the problematic he has expounded. On Hartmann's way of taking

    ontology, cf. his "Wie ist kritische Ontologic ürhaupt möich?", Festschrift für Paul

    Natorp, 1924, pp. 124 ff.

    xvii. ( H. 209 ) Cf. specially Section 16, H. 72 ff. ('How the Worldly Character of the

    Environment Announces itself in Entities Within-the-world'); Section 18, H. 83 ff.

    ('Involvement and Significance; the Worldhood of the World'); Section 29, H. 134 ff.

    ('Dasein as State-of-Mind'). On the Being-in-itself of entities within-the-world, cf. H. 75 f.

xviii. ( H. 209 ) Dilthey, op. cit., p. 134.

xix. ( H. 210 ) Cf. Scheler's lecture, "Die Formen des Wissens und die Bildung", 1925, notes 24

    and 25. In reading our proofs we notice that in the collection of Scheler's treatises which

    has just appeared ( Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft, 1926) he has published his

    long-promised study ' Erkenntnis und Arbeit' (pp. 233 ff.). Division VI of this treatise (p.

    455) brings a more detailed exposition of his 'voluntative theory of Dasein', in connection

    with an evaluation and critique of Dilthey.

    xx. ( H. 212 ) Diels, Fragment 5. [This passage may be translated in more than one way: e.g.,

    for thought and being are the same thing' (Fairbanks); 'it is the same thing that can be

    thought and that can be' (Burnet).Tr.]

xxi. ( H. 212 ) Aristotle, Metaphysica A.

    xxii. ( H. 213 ) Ibid., A, 984a 18 ff. ['. . . the very fact showed them the way and joined in

    forcing them to investigate the subject.' (Ross)Tr.]

xxiii. ( H. 213 ) Ibid. , A, 986b 31.

xxiv. ( H. 213 ) Ibid. , A, 984b 10.

xxv. ( H. 213 ) Ibid. , A, 983b 2. Cf. .988a 20.

xxvi. xxvi.( H. 213 ) Ibid. , aI, 993b 17.

xxvii. ( H. 213 ) Ibid. , aI, 993b 20.

xxviii. ( H. 213 ) Ibid. , I', I, 1003a 21.

xxix. ( H. 214 ) Aristotle, De interpretatione 1, 16a. 6. [This is not an exact quotation.Tr.)

xxx. ( H. 214 ) Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate, qu. I, art. I.

xxxi.. ( H. 215 ) Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 2 p. 82.

    xxxii. ( H. 215 ) Ibid., p. 83 . [Two trivial misprints in this quotation which appear in the earlier

    editions have been corrected in the later editions.Tr.]

    xxxiii. ( H. 215 ) Ibid., p. 350 . [Another trivial misprint has been corrected in the later

    editions.Tr.]

xxxiv. ( H. 218 ) On the idea of demonstration as 'identification' el. Husserl, Logische 2Untersuchungen, Vol. II, part 2, Untersuchung VI. On 'evidence and truth' see ibid. ,

    Sections 36-39, pp. 115 ff. The usual presentations of the phenomenological theory

    -493-

     of truth confine themselves to what has been said in the critical prolegomena (vol. 1),

    and mention that this is connected with Bolzano's theory of the proposition. But the

    positive phenomenological Interpretations, which differ basically from Bolzano's theory,

    have been neglected. The only person who has taken up these investigations positively

    from outside the main stream of phenomenological research, has been E. Lask whose

    Logik der Philosophie ( 1911) was as strongly influenced by the sixth Untersuchung

    ( "Über sinnliche und kategoriale Anschauungen", pp. 128 ff.) as his Lehre vom Urteil

    ( 1912) was influenced by the above-mentioned sections on evidence and truth.

xxxv. ( H. 219 ) Cf. Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, Heracleitus fragment B 1.

xxxvi. ( H. 220 ) Cf. H. 32 ff.

xxxvii. ( H. 221 ) Cf. H. 134 ff.

xxxviii. ( H. 221 ) Cf. H. 166 ff.

xxxix. ( H. 223 ) Karl Reinhardt (Cf. his Parmenides und die Geschichte der grieschischen

    Philosophie, 1916) was the first to conceptualize and solve the hackneyed problem of

    how the two parts of Parmenides' poem are connected, though he did not explicitly point

    out the ontological foundation for the connection between λ?,?Θεια and δó?α, or its

    necessity.

    xl. ( H. 223 ) Cf. Section 33 above, H. 153 ff. ('Assertion as a derivative mode of

    interpretation.')

xli. ( H. 223 ) Cf. Section 34, H. 160 ff.

xlii. ( H. 225 ) Cf. Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea Z and Metaphysicae ? 10.

    Division Two, Section 45

    i. ( H. 231 ) Cf. Section 9, H. 41 ff.

ii. ( H. 231 ) Cf. Section 6, H. 19 ff.; Section 21, H. 93 ff.; Section 43, H. 201.

iii. ( H. 232 ) Cf. Section 32, H. 148 ff.

iv. ( H. 232 ) Cf. Section 9, H. 41 ff.

v. ( H. 233 ) Cf. Section 41, H. 191 ff.

vi. ( H. 235 ) In the nineteenth century, Søren Kierkegaard explicitly seized upon the problem

    of existence as an existentiell problem, and thought it through in a penetrating fashion. But

    the existential problematic was so alien to him that, as regards his ontology, he remained 1completely dominated by Hegel and by ancient philosophy as Hegel saw it. Thus, there is

    more to be learned philosophically from his 'edifying' writings than from his theoretical

    oneswith the exception of his treatise on the concept of anxiety. [Here Heidegger is

    referring to the work generally known in English as The Concept of Dread.Tr.]

    Division Two, Chapter One

    i. ( H. 240 ) Cf. Section 9, H. 41 ff.

ii. ( H. 241 ) Cf. Section 10, H. 45 ff.

iii. ( H. 244 ) The distinction between a whole and a sum, λον and πâν, totum and

    compositum, has been familiar since the time of Plato and Aristotle. But admittedly no one

    as yet knows anything about the systematics of the categorial variations which this division

    already embraces, nor have these been conceptualized. As an approach to a thorough

    analysis of the structures in question, cf. Edmund Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, vol.

    II, Untersuchung III: "Zur Lehre von den Ganzen und Teilen".

iv. ( H. 245 ) Der Ackermann aus Böhmen, edited by A.Bernt and K. Burdach. ( Vom

    Mittelalter zur Reformation. Forschungen zur Geschichte der deutschen Bildung, edited by

    K. Burdach, vol. III, 2. Teil) 1917, chapter 20, p. 46.

v. ( H. 246 ) On this topic, of the comprehensive presentation in E. Korschelt's Lebensdauer,

    Altern und Tod, 3rd Edition, 1924. Note especially the full bibliography, pp. 414 ff.

vi. ( H. 249 ) In its Interpretation of 'life', the anthropology worked out in Christian theology

    from Paul right up to Calvin's meditatio futurae vitaehas always kept death in view.

    Wilhelm Dilthey, whose real philosophical tendencies were aimed at an ontology of 'life',

    could not fail to recognize how life is connected with death: '. . . and finally, that

    relationship which most deeply and universally determines the feeling of our Daseinthe

    relationship of life to death; for the bounding of our existence by death is always decisive

    for our understanding and assessment of life.' ( Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung, 5th Edition,

    p. 230.) Recently, G. Simmel has also explicitly included the

____________________ 1Here we follow the older editions in reading '. . . und der durch diesen gesehencn antiken

    Philosophie . . .' In the new editions 'gesehenen' has been changed to 'geschehenen'.

    -494-

     phenomenon of death in his characterization of 'life', though admittedly without clearly

    separating the biological-ontical and the ontological-existential problematics. (Cf. his

    Lebrnsanschauung:Vier Metaphysische Kapitel, 1918, pp. 99-153.) For the investigation

    which lies before us, compare especially Karl Jaspers' Psychologie der Weltanschauungen,

    3rd Edition, 1925, pp. 229 ff., especially pp. 259-270. Jaspers takes as his clue to death the

    phenomenon of the 'limit-situation' as he has set it fortha phenomenon whose

    fundamental significance goes beyond any typology of 'attitudes' and 'world-pictures'.

    Dilthey's challenges have been taken up by Rudolf Unger in his Herder, Novalis und Kleist.

    Studien über die Entwicklung des Todesproblems im Denken und Dichten von Sturm und

    Drang zur Romantik, 1922. In his lecture 'Literaturgeschichte als Problemgeschichte. Zur

    Frage geisteshistorischer Synthese, mit besonderer Bezichung auf Wilhelm Dilthey'

    ( Schriften der Königsberger Gelehrten Gesellschaft, Geisteswissenschaftliche Klasse, 1.

    Jahr, Heft 1, 1924), Unger considers the principles of Dilthey's way of formulating the

    question. He sees clearly the significance of phenomenological research for laying the

Report this document

For any questions or suggestions please email
cust-service@docsford.com